Show simple item record

Files in this item

Thumbnail

Item metadata

dc.contributor.authorWeatherson, Brian James
dc.date.accessioned2016-07-12T15:30:03Z
dc.date.available2016-07-12T15:30:03Z
dc.date.issued2016
dc.identifier244241593
dc.identifier01713948-2af8-4a88-8f72-ae5d219c605a
dc.identifier85049138247
dc.identifier.citationWeatherson , B J 2016 , ' Reply to Blackson ' , Journal of Philosophical Research , vol. 41 , pp. 73-75 . https://doi.org/10.5840/jpr201663072en
dc.identifier.issn2153-7984
dc.identifier.urihttps://hdl.handle.net/10023/9120
dc.description.abstractThomas Blackson argues that interest-relative epistemologies cannot explain the irrationality of certain choices when the agent has three possible options. I argue that his examples only refute a subclass of interest-relative theories. In particular, they are good objections to theories that say that what an agent knows depends on the stakes involved in the gambles that she faces. But they are not good objections to theories that say that what an agent knows depends on the odds involved in the gambles that she faces. Indeed, the latter class of theories does a better job than interest-invariant epistemologies of explaining the phenomena he describes.
dc.format.extent37626
dc.language.isoeng
dc.relation.ispartofJournal of Philosophical Researchen
dc.subjectB Philosophy (General)en
dc.subject.lccB1en
dc.titleReply to Blacksonen
dc.typeJournal articleen
dc.contributor.institutionUniversity of St Andrews. School of Philosophical, Anthropological and Film Studiesen
dc.contributor.institutionUniversity of St Andrews. Philosophyen
dc.identifier.doi10.5840/jpr201663072
dc.description.statusPeer revieweden


This item appears in the following Collection(s)

Show simple item record