Show simple item record

Files in this item

Thumbnail

Item metadata

dc.contributor.authorSnedegar, Justin
dc.date.accessioned2020-11-05T00:38:08Z
dc.date.available2020-11-05T00:38:08Z
dc.date.issued2019-09-27
dc.identifier256174085
dc.identifierfb780b0e-4514-4600-9890-3a21d6770676
dc.identifier85056088613
dc.identifier000487838700001
dc.identifier.citationSnedegar , J 2019 , ' Deliberation, reasons, and alternatives ' , Pacific Philosophical Quarterly , vol. 100 , no. 3 , pp. 682-702 . https://doi.org/10.1111/papq.12262en
dc.identifier.issn0279-0750
dc.identifier.otherORCID: /0000-0002-2552-0702/work/64697915
dc.identifier.urihttps://hdl.handle.net/10023/20903
dc.description.abstractA plausible constraint on normative reasons to act is that it must make sense to use them as premises in deliberation. I argue that a central sort of deliberation – what Bratman calls partial planning – is question‐directed: it is over, and aims to resolve, deliberative questions. Whether it makes sense to use some consideration as a premise in deliberation in a case of partial planning can vary with the deliberative question at issue. I argue that the best explanation for this is that reasons are contrastive or relativized to deliberative questions.
dc.format.extent234485
dc.language.isoeng
dc.relation.ispartofPacific Philosophical Quarterlyen
dc.subjectDeliberationen
dc.subjectReasonsen
dc.subjectAlternativesen
dc.subjectEthicsen
dc.subjectReasoningen
dc.subjectB Philosophy (General)en
dc.subjectT-NDASen
dc.subject.lccB1en
dc.titleDeliberation, reasons, and alternativesen
dc.typeJournal articleen
dc.contributor.institutionUniversity of St Andrews. Philosophyen
dc.identifier.doi10.1111/papq.12262
dc.description.statusPeer revieweden
dc.date.embargoedUntil2020-11-05


This item appears in the following Collection(s)

Show simple item record