Show simple item record

Files in this item

Thumbnail

Item metadata

dc.contributor.authorSachs, Benjamin
dc.date.accessioned2016-07-07T14:30:15Z
dc.date.available2016-07-07T14:30:15Z
dc.date.issued2017-01-08
dc.identifier243534336
dc.identifierb1849b48-0414-4cc8-9694-4a310bff376c
dc.identifier85009458793
dc.identifier000411999600003
dc.identifier.citationSachs , B 2017 , ' Fair equality of opportunity in our actual world ' , Theory and Research in Education , vol. 14 , no. 3 , pp. 277-294 . https://doi.org/10.1177/1477878516676712en
dc.identifier.issn1477-8785
dc.identifier.otherORCID: /0000-0002-2307-7620/work/69029289
dc.identifier.urihttps://hdl.handle.net/10023/9088
dc.description.abstractFair equality of opportunity, a principle that governs the competition for desirable jobs, can seem irrelevant in our actual world, for two reasons. First, parents have broad liberty to raise their children as they see fit, which seems to undermine the fair equality of opportunity–based commitment to eliminating the effects of social circumstances on that competition. Second, we already have a well-established principle for distributing jobs, namely meritocracy, thereby leaving no theater in which fair equality of opportunity can operate. I argue that we can solve both of these problems by conceding, in contrast to previous fair equality of opportunity defenders, that there’s no unique good associated with the right job, while insisting that there is a unique bad associated with the wrong job and holding that fair equality of opportunity should govern the competition to avoid that bad by attaining the right job. This move enables new responses to the two problems previously mentioned. In response to the meritocracy problem, I propose simply accepting that that principle should guide the distribution of jobs and all the associated goods while maintaining that there is room for a separate, non-consequentialist principle whose function is to ensure a fair distribution of chances to avoid the unique bad just identified. In response to the parental liberty problem, I argue that, for any given person, which job will deliver the unique bad I identify is contingent on her skills, and therefore, the way she is raised determines what would constitute a bad employment outcome for her, but doesn’t affect her chances of avoiding that outcome.
dc.format.extent18
dc.format.extent191117
dc.language.isoeng
dc.relation.ispartofTheory and Research in Educationen
dc.subjectEquality of opportunityen
dc.subjectJobsen
dc.subjectJohn Rawlsen
dc.subjectMeritocracyen
dc.subjectParental libertyen
dc.subjectLB Theory and practice of educationen
dc.subjectB Philosophy (General)en
dc.subjectT-NDASen
dc.subject.lccLBen
dc.subject.lccB1en
dc.titleFair equality of opportunity in our actual worlden
dc.typeJournal articleen
dc.contributor.institutionUniversity of St Andrews. Philosophyen
dc.contributor.institutionUniversity of St Andrews. St Andrews Centre for Exoplanet Scienceen
dc.contributor.institutionUniversity of St Andrews. Institute of Legal and Constitutional Researchen
dc.identifier.doi10.1177/1477878516676712
dc.description.statusPeer revieweden


This item appears in the following Collection(s)

Show simple item record