Show simple item record

Files in this item

Thumbnail

Item metadata

dc.contributor.advisorEtinson, Adam
dc.contributor.advisorBrown, Jessica (Jessica Anne)
dc.contributor.authorHinze, Jakob
dc.coverage.spatialxvi, 192 p.en_US
dc.date.accessioned2021-06-14T15:57:57Z
dc.date.available2021-06-14T15:57:57Z
dc.date.issued2021-06-28
dc.identifier.urihttps://hdl.handle.net/10023/23356
dc.description.abstractAt the core of democracy is a simple idea: one person, one vote. However, all democracies disenfranchise citizens below a certain age. What justifies this practice? The answer seems obvious: voting isn’t a children’s game. When citizens head to the ballots, a lot is at stake: who runs the government and what policies are implemented significantly affects the lives of many citizens. According to a widely held view, voting requires a certain competence that children lack. If we take this idea a little further, we may conclude that adult citizens ought to demonstrate a certain level of competence before receiving the right to vote, too. However, most contemporary political philosophers reject this “epistocratic” line of thought. Either for epistemic, moral, or pragmatic reasons, they endorse enfranchising every adult. This raises the central question of this dissertation: can we justify giving the right to vote to all and only citizens above a certain age? I argue that we cannot. To establish this claim, I assess three different voting schemes: Standard Democracy, which gives exactly one vote to all and only citizens above a certain age; Epistocratic Democracy, which gives more voting power to “politically knowledgeable” citizens; and Ageless Democracy, which gives all citizens, regardless of age, the right to cast exactly one vote in democratic procedures. First, I defend Standard Democracy against Epistocratic Democracy. This amounts to an argument that all citizens above a certain age should have equal voting rights. I then evaluate potential justifications for conceding these rights only to citizens above a certain age, and reject them. This amounts to a case for Ageless Democracy. Abandoning the voting age is both a theoretically consistent implication of rejecting Epistocratic Democracy and a practically desirable approach to reinvigorating democratic procedures.en_US
dc.language.isoenen_US
dc.publisherUniversity of St Andrews
dc.rightsCreative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International*
dc.rights.urihttp://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/*
dc.subjectVoting rightsen_US
dc.subjectEpistemic democracyen_US
dc.subjectEpistocracyen_US
dc.subjectChildrenen_US
dc.subject.lccJF841.H5
dc.subject.lcshVoting ageen
dc.subject.lcshSuffrage--Philosophyen
dc.titleRejuvenating democracy : age, knowledge, and the right to voteen_US
dc.typeThesisen_US
dc.contributor.sponsorPhilosophical Quarterlyen_US
dc.contributor.sponsorSociety of Applied Philosophyen_US
dc.contributor.sponsorUniversity of St Andrews. St Leonard's Collegeen_US
dc.type.qualificationlevelDoctoralen_US
dc.type.qualificationnamePhD Doctor of Philosophyen_US
dc.publisher.institutionThe University of St Andrewsen_US
dc.identifier.doihttps://doi.org/10.17630/sta/74


The following licence files are associated with this item:

    This item appears in the following Collection(s)

    Show simple item record

    Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International
    Except where otherwise noted within the work, this item's licence for re-use is described as Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International