Show simple item record

Files in this item

Thumbnail

Item metadata

dc.contributor.advisorTimmermann, Jens
dc.contributor.authorSchaab, Janis David
dc.coverage.spatialx, 191 p.en_US
dc.date.accessioned2019-03-26T12:42:28Z
dc.date.available2019-03-26T12:42:28Z
dc.date.issued2019-06-24
dc.identifier.urihttps://hdl.handle.net/10023/17374
dc.description.abstractThis thesis provides a restatement of Kantian constructivism, with the aim of avoiding some of the objections and clearing up some of the ambiguities that have haunted previous versions of the view. I restate Kantian constructivism as the view that morality’s normativity has its source in the form of second-personal reasoning, a mode of practical reasoning in which we engage when we address demands person-to-person. By advancing a position about the source of moral normativity, Kantian constructivism addresses a metaethical question, albeit one that is distinct from the questions that many traditional metaethical positions, such as moral realism, focus on. Kantian constructivism has an advantage over competing views of the source of moral normativity when it comes to answering the so-called Normative Question, which I interpret as the question of why we are rationally required to do what we take to be our moral obligation. Kantian constructivism can answer this question because, unlike its competitors, it does not conceive of practical reason as a receptive faculty that is determined by external inputs. Instead, it regards the very form of second-personal reasoning as grounding the fact that morality is normative, thus explaining morality’s rational authority. Although second-personal reasoning is fundamentally distinct from the merely first-personal mode of reasoning that we must engage in insofar as we are agents, all those agents whom we would ordinarily consider bound by moral obligations seem to engage in it. Indeed, although it involves irreducibly second-personal notions, such as accountability and the authority to address legitimate demands, second-personal reasoning is not to be mistaken for a social practice. Instead, it can be applied to purely self-regarding contexts, such as that of committing oneself to a personal project and thereby holding oneself accountable for pursuing it, as well as to interactions with others.en_US
dc.language.isoenen_US
dc.publisherUniversity of St Andrews
dc.rightsAttribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International*
dc.rights.urihttp://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/*
dc.subjectEthicsen_US
dc.subjectKanten_US
dc.subjectPhilosophyen_US
dc.subjectMetaethicsen_US
dc.subjectPractical reasonen_US
dc.subject.lccBJ1458.3S2
dc.subject.lcshNormativity (Ethics)en
dc.subject.lcshKant, Immanuel, 1724-1804--Contributions in ethicsen
dc.subject.lcshMetaethicsen
dc.subject.lcshPractical reasonen
dc.titleKantian constructivism: a restatementen_US
dc.typeThesisen_US
dc.contributor.sponsorAristotelian Society (Great Britain)en_US
dc.contributor.sponsorUniversity of St. Andrews. Centre for Ethics, Philosophy and Public Affairsen_US
dc.contributor.sponsorErasmus+ (Program)en_US
dc.contributor.sponsorUniversity of St Andrews. Department of Philosophyen_US
dc.contributor.sponsorRussell Trusten_US
dc.contributor.sponsorSantander UK. Santander Universitiesen_US
dc.type.qualificationlevelDoctoralen_US
dc.type.qualificationnamePhD Doctor of Philosophyen_US
dc.publisher.institutionThe University of St Andrewsen_US
dc.publisher.departmentUniversity of Stirlingen_US
dc.rights.embargoreasonEmbargo period has ended, thesis made available in accordance with University regulationsen
dc.identifier.doihttps://doi.org/10.17630/10023-17374


The following licence files are associated with this item:

    This item appears in the following Collection(s)

    Show simple item record

    Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International
    Except where otherwise noted within the work, this item's licence for re-use is described as Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International